The Good (in churlish brevity)
Ive just finished reading Noam Chomskys Imperial Ambitions: Conversations on the Post-9/11 World (it was a Christmas gift). Unsurprisingly, nearly all of it is excellent, and I highly recommend it. Chomsky lucidly explains how u.s. foreign policy is not only imperialist now but has been so since the beginning; and he shows how the u.s. perpetually justifies its expansionism by exaggerating the threat posed by its victims. (The u.s. comes across a bit like the Daleks immensely powerful but constantly in hysterical panic.) Admittedly its not one of Chomskys most important works its just a collection of interviews but its a quicker read than, and might work well as an introduction to, those more important works.
But rather than elaborating on the 97.3% thats terrific in the book, I cant resist grumping about the 2.7% that is not so great.
The Ugly
Probably the worst item in the book is this one: I was never against the draft, and Im not against it now. If there is going to be an army, I think it should be a citizens army, not a mercenary army. (p. 132) Chomsky doesnt say what penalty he proposes to inflict on those who refuse the call-up. But the prospect of the u.s.s most prominent anarchist endorsing forced labor particularly forced labor that involves killing and being killed is a bit stomach-turning. I dont want to go to war today, but the lord of the lash says nay nay nay and the lord of the lash turns out to be Noam fucking Chomsky! Good grief. (And his later effusive praise for the courage of draft resisters (p. 156) only makes it creepier.)
The Merely Bad
His support for military slavery aside, my other gripes, as with my previous criticisms of Chomsky (see here and here), concern those areas where Chomsky seems either to fall into left-conflationism or to lack the courage of his anarchist convictions by overestimating the merits of governmental solutions. (But maybe those are just two different sides of the same mistake.)
Chomsky certainly isnt consistently conflationist; on the contrary, in this very book he writes, about the Bush administration:
They dont want a small government any more than Reagan did. They want a huge, massively intrusive government, but one that works for them. They hate free markets. (p. 113)
And he offers insightful analysis of some of the ways in which corporatism operates (see, e.g., pp. 56-58, 193-195).
Yet on the other hand he condemns Republican faux-privatisation efforts for transferring decisions out of the public arena into private hands (p. 15), as though the government represented a public arena in any meaningful sense even though Chomsky has done as much as anyone to show that it doesnt. (Actually, transferring decisions from governmental to private hands would make for far more accountability much more of a public arena or (in Mises sense) an economic democracy if what were involved were a genuinely freed market rather than, as it actually is, a morass of corporate privilege.)
Moreover, Chomsky offers up a bizarre pæan to Social Security:
Social Security is based on a principle that is considered subversive … the principle that you care about other people. Social Security is based on the assumption that we care about each other, that we have a communal responsibility to take care of people who cant take care of themselves …. We have a social responsibility to pay for schools, to ensure day care …. Social Security was created in response to pressure from popular, organized social movements the labor movement and others that were based on the idea of solidarity and mutual aid. … At one time, the principle of solidarity was taken for granted. It was a fundamental feature of popular movements. … And ever since the 1930s, the privileged and wealthy have been dedicated to trying to eliminate this principle. … And thats what really lies behind the attack on Social Security. (pp. 145-7; cf. p. 25)
Even leaving aside the fact that Social Security has always been marketed (albeit dishonestly) as a forced-saving scheme rather than a redistributive one Chomskys supposed link between Social Security and mutual aid both ignores the distinction between coerced and voluntary exchange, and defies the historical record. Social Security and other such coercive welfare programs were part of a concerted effort mostly on the part of the privileged and wealthy to displace the voluntary programs of solidarity and mutual aid. The A.M.A., for example, used its government-granted licensing powers to threaten physicians with the destruction of their careers if they dared to undercut the revenue of the privileged by signing up with fraternal societies. Why is an anarchist praising such solidarity-smashing policies? (For more skeptical anarchist assessments of Social Security, see David Beito and Kevin Carson.)
Now Id understand if Chomsky were simply saying that, given that the state has deprived us of voluntary alternatives, we need to keep Social Security and the like at present essentially, that a government that breaks your leg and then hands you a crutch is better than a government that breaks your leg and then doesnt hand you a crutch. But that doesnt seem to be what hes saying.
(Chomsky also tosses off in passing the economic howler that free trade cant work in the context of free capital movement (p. 147) as though imaginary lines on a map could magically defeat the mutually beneficial nature of voluntary exchange.)
In addition, Chomsky describes Social Security, risibly, as a highly efficient government system, with very low administrative costs. But Chomsky seems to be as inconsistent on the states efficiency as he is on its beneficence. On the one hand, he clearly grasps the La Boétian/Humean point (even citing Hume) that:
[I]n any state, whether a democratic state or a totalitarian state, the rulers rely on consent. They have to make sure that the people they are ruling do not understand that they actually have the power. That is the fundamental principle of government. (p. 153)
Yet on the other hand, Chomsky seems to ignore this insight in exaggerating the effectiveness of centralised power. For example, he expresses surprise at the inability of American military force to put down the insurgency in Iraq:
[T]o my amazement, the occupation is not succeeding. It takes real talent to fail in this. For one thing, military occupations almost always work. … Furthermore, Iraq is an unusually easy case. Here is a country that has been decimated by a decade of murderous sanctions that killed hundreds of thousands of people and left the whole place in tatters, devastated by wars, and run by a brutal tyrant. The idea that you cant get a military occupation to run under these circumstances … is almost inconceivable. … The occupation of Iraq has been an astonishing failure. The administrations original planning … amazingly looks like it isnt going to work. … Its a big surprise to me. I thought this would be a walkover. (pp. 46-47)
Between the informational diseconomies of scale involved in top-down control and Chomskys own invocation of a governed populaces La Boétian/Humean ability to resist such control, its odd that Chomsky should be surprised at the failure of military occupation. Wasnt the ineffectiveness of top-down occupation one of the lessons of Vietnam? Well, not for Chomsky:
Im one of the few people who dont agree that the United States lost the war in Vietnam. … There is no way for a huge, powerful state to lose a war against a defenseless enemy. It just cant happen. (pp. 120-121)
What happened to the power of the ruled and the impotence of the rulers being the fundamental principle of government? If it really is impossible for a subject population to prevail against a powerful state, as he asserts here, then Chomskys entire political career has been a futile endeavour. But against this defeatist Chomsky, awed by the majesty of the state, who tells us that there is no way for a huge, powerful state to lose a war against a defenseless enemy, I would quote the more optimistic and more anarchistic Chomsky who understands that in any state … the rulers rely on consent and have to make sure that the people they are ruling do not understand that they actually have the power. Its as though Chomsky sometimes remembers his anarchist analysis and sometimes forgets it.
It is perhaps significant that one of Chomskys books features on its cover, in Chomskys words, a U.S. soldier …. with a rope pulling a skinny, half-naked Vietnamese captive behind him (p. 119), while Kevin Carson considered using for the cover of his most recent book a photo of a tiny teenage Viet Cong girl leading an enormous captive American soldier. The contrast between those two images eloquently sums up the difference between an anarchism that stands in awe of the state and one that holds it in contempt.
Chomskys tendency to leave his anarchism in the lurch also manifests itself in his insistence on the importance of voting for the lesser of two evils. With regard to the Bush-Kerry race, Chomsky grants that the two sides are not fantastically different, but nevertheless insists that since Kerry would be more likely to protect some limited form of benefits for the general population, it would be irresponsible not to vote for Kerry:
Anyone who says, I dont care if Bush gets elected is basically telling poor and working people in the country, I dont care if your lives are destroyed …. because from my elevated point of view I dont see much of a difference between the two candidates. Thats a way of saying, Pay no attention to me, because I dont care about you. Apart from its being wrong, its a recipe for disaster if youre hoping ever to develop a popular movement and a political alternative. (p. 114)
Here Chomsky makes it sound as though he recognises no way of working to improve the lives of the oppressed except through electoral politics. Of course he doesnt think any such thing consistently; on the contrary, he praises SNCC and the feminist movement for campaigns to change the culture that went far beyond the ballot box. (pp. 155-160) Yet at other times he seems to think that the point of cultural change is simply to serve as a handmaiden to the ballot box after all: Unless you develop an ongoing, living, democratic culture that can compel the candidates, he solemnly informs us, theyre not going to do the things you voted for. (p. 91) Yet surely for an anarchist, particularly one who understands the La Boétian/Humean insight that the power of the rulers depends on the acquiescence of the ruled, the point of developing an ongoing, living, democratic culture should be not to direct the state but to render it irrelevant by withdrawing support from it in favour of voluntary, egalitarian relationships and institutions.
Given the extent to which Chomsky seems un-anarchistically impressed by the merits of conventional political action, he comes across as somewhat unfair in complaining that people in the u.s. are always asking him what they can do about the political and social problems he discusses:
After every talk I give in the United States, people come up and say, I want to change things. What can I do? I never hear these questions from peasants in southern Colombia, Kurds in southeastern Turkey under miserable repression, or anybody who is suffering. They dont ask what they can do; they tell you what theyre doing. Somehow the fact of enormous privilege and freedom carries with it a sense of impotence …. There is no difficulty in finding and joining groups that are working hard on issues that concern you. (p. 90; cf. p. 39)
Chomsky seems not to have considered the possibility that the answer to this question is less obvious than he supposes. Sure, its easy to find groups that are working hard on issues that concern you; but what strategy are they pursuing? Are they working to get nicer masters into the top slots of the power structure, or are they working to undermine the power structure as such? Anarchism is the only political philosophy that doesnt require its adherents to gain control of the state apparatus (whether through violent revolution or peaceful elections) in order to implement it. As an anarchist, Chomsky should be open to the possibility that the best strategy for sociopolitical change might be different from those based on the political means. To drag out again two of my favourite anarchist quotations:
The state is a relationship between human beings, a way by which people relate to one another; and one destroys it by entering into other relationships, by behaving differently to one another. (Gustav Landauer)
A free society cannot be the substitution of a new order for the old order; it is the extension of spheres of free action until they make up most of social life. (Paul Goodman)
In this light the question of what to do becomes more pressing, and the answer join a group thats working on your issues seems less than helpful. The real question is: should I join a group thats mainly about entering into other relationships and the extension of spheres of free action, or one thats focused primarily on changing the personnel roster of the corporate state?
(As for the greater tendency for the question what can I do? to be asked by the more privileged, this might well be explained less by a sense of impotence than by the existence of a greater range of options. The more options one has, the more advice one needs as to which option to pick.)
I have a related concern about Chomskys remarks on ideological change. In response to Antonio Gramscis call to develop alternative interpretations of reality in order to counter the reproduction by the dominated forces of elements of the hegemonic ideology, Chomsky is surprisingly dismissive: all one has to do is tell the truth, he says, and Gramscis concern is just an example of how intellectuals internalize the conception that they have to make things seem complicated. … How complicated is it to understand the truth or to know how to act? (pp. 63-64) There are no techniques for countering propaganda, just ordinary common sense. (p. 32)
My worry here is that when people are in the grip of a particular picture of the world, merely reciting facts to them, even if theyre persuaded, is going to be of limited utility; if one has been conditioned to believe that existing power structures are essentially benign, then one will tend to treat counterexamples as accidental, as exceptional, as a few rotten apples or waste, fraud, and abuse or friction rather than as symptomatic of an inherently flawed system.
And Chomsky sometimes knows this; he reminds us, for example, that journalists generally have professional integrity and are honest, serious professionals who want to do their job properly, but most of them reflexively perceive the world through a particular prism that happens to be supportive of concentrated power. (p. 150) So just throwing facts at people who will view those facts through their distorting prism fails to address the problem of the prism itself.
Now its true, as Ive discussed before (see here and here), that repeated and prolonged exposure to anomalous cases can make it easier for those in the grip of a flawed conceptual scheme to find their way out of it. But its equally true, as Thomas Kuhn points out, that people are generally reluctant to abandon a conceptual scheme unless there is an alternative to switch to and this is the Gramscian point that Chomsky is dismissing. Its a fatal dismissal, because, as Ive been trying to show, Chomsky does not really have a consistent alternate scheme himself to offer; instead he vacillates between two incompatible schemes one progressive-reformist and one anarchist.
Let me close by reiterating that what is valuable in Chomskys book far outweighs what is flawed. So go read it!